47 pages • 1 hour read
Samuel Taylor ColeridgeA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Coleridge critiques Hartley’s ideas about mental associations, claiming that they confuse the issue of causality. Nor does Coleridge agree with Hume, whom he writes “degraded the notion of cause and effect into a blind product of delusion and habit” (37). Rather, “contemporaneity” is a law of the mind (37). A water insect jumping upstream is “no unapt emblem of the mind’s self experience in the act of thinking” (38). Thinking thus involves an “intermediate faculty, which is at once both active and passive” (38). Coleridge calls this “imagination” (38). Finally, he recommends “a condition free from anxieties” (39) to facilitate accurate perception.
Next, Coleridge critiques Cartesian dualism, as refined by Spinoza and Leibnitz. He finds Hylozoism and materialism no more convincing. Hylozoism he finds muddy, and materialism fails to explain the origin of consciousness: “in order to explain the thinking as a material phenomena, it is necessary to refine matter into a mere modification of intelligence” (41). Coleridge concludes that the origin of consciousness remains a problem. Attempting to fathom it, “we might as rationally charged the Brahim creed of the tortoise that supported the bear, that supported the elephant, that supported the world, to the tune of ‘This is the house that Jack built,’” Coleridge jokes (42).
Coleridge now queries the feasibility of philosophy as a science. Philosophy is “seeking after the truth; but truth is the correlative of being” (43). Even the Neoplatonists refrained to “pass beyond a certain limit in speculative science” (44). Instead, Coleridge relies on the mystics, since “the true depth of science, and the penetration to the inmost center, from which all the lines of knowledge diverge […] was abandoned” (44). Coleridge is also sympathetic to Kant’s Noumenon, or the “thing in itself” (45), and Schelling, a “great and original genius” (47). The chapter ends with a discussion of indebtedness among philosophical thinkers.
Coleridge enters into the philosophical phase of Biographia Literaria. His thoughts about literary theory are couched in an argument about the nature of reality itself. Coleridge claims that science avoids addressing the center of reality and thus aligns his theory of poetry with philosophy. Still, poetry is better able to penetrate reality than philosophy, since philosophy pursues knowledge and not being itself. Kant’s Noumenon, or “thing in itself,” influenced Coleridge. (Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. 1783.) Kant’s 1781 Critique of Pure Reason also furnished Coleridge with his ideas about what Kant called intellectual “intuition.” While Coleridge’s contemporaries debated what Kant meant by “transcendental idealism,” Coleridge himself disagrees with Kant’s claim that the “transcendental object cannot even be separated from the sensible data, for then nothing would remain through which it would be thought” (Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. 1781.) For Coleridge, the ultimate nature of reality is transmittable via the plastic power of the Imagination.
In his exposition of philosophical ideas about the nature of reality and perception, Coleridge envisions the thinking mind as a “water insect” skipping back and forth as it makes its way upstream (99). This Heraclitan metaphor positions the mind outside time. Contemporaneity is “the common condition of all the laws of association” (38), while consciousness is “time considered in its essence” (39). Thus the greatest poetry is not only timeless but capable of provoking a certain kind of meditation that transports the reader outside of time and “into the life of things.” (Wordsworth, William. “Lines Written a Few Miles Above Tintern Abbey.” 1798.) Rather than functioning as a form of memorialization as in Wordsworth, poetry for Coleridge ideally transports us into the eternal.
By Samuel Taylor Coleridge