logo

33 pages 1 hour read

Transl. Thomas Williams, Augustine of Hippo

On Free Choice Of The Will

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 395

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Book 3Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Book 3 Summary

At the beginning of the third book, the dialogue has reached the point where several issues have been resolved, but one thing still remains to discuss in detail: the source of evil. Evodius confronts Augustine: “It has been demonstrated to my satisfaction that free will is to be numbered among good things, and indeed not among the least of them, and therefore that it was given to us by God, who acted rightly in giving it. So now, if you think that this is a good time, I would like you to explain the source of the movement by which the will turns away from the common and unchangeable good toward its own good, or the good of others, or lower goods, all of which are changeable” (70). Evodius is content to say that human beings have free will, and that free will is a good given to human nature by God, but he is still unsure of how it is that this good faculty can be put to wicked use.

Augustine continues with a thought experiment and compares the will to an artifact that is only moved from the outside and by necessity. If the will moves by necessity and cannot do otherwise, then there is no blame to be administered because that would be irrational, so the question becomes: “whose movement is it?” (71). In the case of a stone that falls to the earth, it is surely the stone that moves, but the stone cannot be blamed for this movement because it only falls to the earth by necessity, it’s a natural movement. So even if the soul moves itself in a wicked way, there still must be a determination if the soul is to be blamed for a disordered movement. The soul does, however, have the power to choose between various goods, “the soul is not moved to abandon higher things and love inferior things unless it wills to do so. And so the movement of the stone is natural, but the movement of the soul is voluntary” (72).

This revelation causes Evodius to ask a further question: “I very much wonder how God can have foreknowledge of everything in the future, and yet we do not sin by necessity” (73). Since the sin is known by God to occur, and since God’s knowledge is infallible, then the sin must necessarily occur; and if it must necessarily occur, that seems to intimate that the sins of human beings must be necessary. The final answer to this stream of logic becomes clear: “either we draw the heretical conclusion that God does not foreknow everything in the future; or, if we cannot accept this conclusion, we must admit that sin happens by necessity and not by will” (74). Augustine responds by appealing to the nature of human happiness, and to the concept of necessity and that which occurs against one’s will.

He proceeds by asking if things that occur necessarily occur against the will of the person, but this cannot be so. He then asks if God foreknows that you will be happy in the future, does that mean that you will be happy against your will? This would be an absurdity, for who could be happy against their will? Augustine concludes from this that just because God infallibly knows future actions and events does not mean that they happen by necessity and against the will of the individual person in whom they occur. Analogously, Augustine offers, human memory of past events does not force past events to happen. They are simply remembered to have happened and cannot be changed; Augustine again draws a parallel between these actions and God’s volition.

Moving from this discussion to a broader discussion of nature in general, Augustine and Evodius discuss the value of a creature that can sin as opposed to the value of a creature that cannot (and does not) sin, comparing human beings with angels. They admit that the angelic creature that is free and yet still does not sin is more perfect than the human creature, but this fact does not mean that human beings should not exist (as Evodius fears). The solution to this problem is trust in God’s providence and divine mercy, and the willingness to embrace the good that has been given to us as human creatures: “So if you will to escape from unhappiness, cherish your will to exist. For if you will more and more to exist, you will approach him who exists in the highest degree. And give thanks that you exist now, for even though you are inferior to those who are happy, you are superior to things that do not have even the will to be happy…” (84-85). Even those who are unhappy in the present life, or in the present moment, still have reason to live, to live well, and to be thankful, for they at the very least have the power and the possibility to be happy (a reality that lower forms of existence do not have).

When one is unhappy, however, this is due to sin in some capacity, and as Augustine tells Evodius, “There are two sources of sin: one’s own spontaneous thought, and someone else’s persuasion…. Now both of these are voluntary; just as no one sins unwillingly by his own thought, so no one yields to the evil prompting of another unless his own will consents” (91). Sin finds its source from within the human person in all instances, either because it originates there or because it originates in someone else and yet flowers in the person due to their own voluntary consent. Even here, though, we are reminded of the goodness of creation, for the very fact that a creature can become corrupt means that it was good in the first place. Corruption either harms the creature in question, meaning that it was (and still is) good, or corruption cannot harm it at all, in which case it is not corrupt.

This voluntariness is the source of praise and blame, of reward and condemnation: “Every rational nature that was created with free choice of the will undoubtedly deserves praise if it abides in the highest and unchangeable good…But every nature that does not abide there, and does not will to act so that it might abide there, deserves to be condemned” (97). Corruption is only blameworthy where there is a flaw, and in creatures there can only be a flaw when a flaw is voluntary created or accepted, “so; they are flawed to the extent that they fall away from the design of their maker” (100). This is what it means to say that particular sinful acts are contrary to nature, since they are contrary to the nature with which God brought that particular being into existence. All creatures, therefore, owe something to God by the very fact that they exist; in the case of human beings, “if they have received a will by which they can will to be better, they owe it to him to exercise this will and be what they ought to be” (102).

When the will is not exercised in the manner that it ought to be, however, the will is used in an unworthy manner—this is the root of sin and evil. “Therefore, a perverse will is the cause of all evils,” Augustine asserts, “If such a will were in accordance with nature, it would preserve that nature and not harm it, and so it would not be perverse” (104). With this in mind, Augustine takes the argument all the way back to the beginning, raising a common objection to the argument that he has been developing: “It is therefore more important to ask,” he states, “what the first human being was like when he was created than how his descendants were propagated. For many people think they are being quite clever by posing this question: “If the first man was created wise, why was he led astray?” (118).

Augustine thus proposes that there is a middle state between wisdom and folly: if the first man was perfectly wise then he should not have fallen and sinned; if he was foolish, then he could not possibly have been wise; if he existed in a liminal state between the two, however, the will could have moved in either direction. The human was capable of wisdom, without possessing it perfectly from the start: “By reason one becomes capable of receiving a commandment to which one ought to be faithful, so that one does what is commanded. The nature of reason grasps the commandment, and obedience to the commandment brings wisdom” (119). In the case of Adam, reason was not enough to prevent the fall from grace, as he succumbed to the second source of evil—another’s persuasion.

Book 3 Analysis

In the final book, the dialogue partners dive into the nuances of the question that prompted the work from the beginning. At the start of Book 1, Evodius asked if God were the cause of evil. Here, Evodius goes further with his inquiry: “I would like you to explain the source of the movement by which the will turns away from the common and unchangeable good toward its own good, or the good of others, or lower goods, all of which are changeable” (70). The reader, having followed the discussion thus far, will understand that the turning of the will from higher, unchangeable goods towards lower good is the sinful act that is in question. As always, every sin involves the choosing of a good, the problem of course is that this good is an inordinate good: either by being inappropriate for the person, for the time, or in the particular circumstances.

The free will, as the power by which the person desires and pursues particular goods, must be the cause of evil for it is only the person who is a cause of evil in the sense that actions are chosen that fall short of the true good. When the movement of the will is voluntary, the will is culpable for its actions, for good or for ill. Now the will is ordered necessarily to a certain extent: the will is ordered towards the good by nature, it cannot be otherwise. However, if the will moved by absolute necessity in the sense that it was not free to make choices, the will (and thus the person) would not be culpable for moral evil, in the same way that it would not be responsible for moral good. In the example of the stone that Augustine gives, it is clear that no one is blaming the stone for falling to the earth, or for rolling down a hill, the stone is simply obedient to the gravity and the laws of nature. If the will were necessarily determined, the will would be no more culpable for any number of wicked acts than would a rock be condemned as sinful for falling to the ground.

Augustine has already shown that the will is praised and acts well when it desires and loves the highest things: goodness, truth, God. Evodius counters this response by questioning how human acts can be truly free when God has foreknowledge of them in an infallible manner. It would seem that if God knows without doubt the actions of any human being, then that human is necessarily locked into those actions; thus, if he or she is locked into those actions as infallibly known by God, it does not seem that they can be called properly voluntary. First, Augustine responds by stating that this cannot be true of God in himself, for even though God knows all that he will do, that does not force any necessity on God, for God is perfectly free. Second, in the case of creatures, divine foreknowledge does not cause things to occur necessarily against the will, for by definition the will can only act in a way that is voluntary. People can be coerced into acting a certain way against their will physically (e.g., getting pushed into a pool, or thrown out of a plane, or locked into a room), but the will can never be violently coerced against itself, it is impossible.

Augustine uses the example of happiness to illustrate the point. If God foresees happiness for someone, is that person somehow bound to be happy necessarily, involuntarily and against their own will? That would be absurd, Augustine says, for nobody could be happy against their own will. This demonstrates that human beings have free will and that divine foreknowledge does not in fact destroy human freedom. The human mind possesses an analogous power in the faculty of memory: the memory recalls certain events of the past, and those events cannot be otherwise than as they happened. As God exists outside of time, God’s existence is eternal presence. It is the experience of the whole of time and space and eternity in a single glance, a single moment. Thus, God’s knowledge of the future is only “future” to the human person, but it is not future to God himself, and is thus almost like human memory that can recall moments from disparate times and places at any point in the present.

Angels, like humans, are rational and individual and possess intellect and (free)will. The angels, however, both have free will and are incapable of sin since they persist in their will eternally. Human beings, as rational animals, exist in the space between the angels and the lower animals in the hierarchy of being, and as such we humans should be content with our place. Since Augustine already determined that inordinate desire is the root cause of all sin, it would be a sinful desire to envy the position of the angels and wish that we humans could avoid the possibility of sin as well. As such, we should be grateful for the chance to be rational, to be possessed of a spiritual soul with an intellect and a will. This conscious act of thanksgiving will be how we make progress in the mortal quest for perfection. In fact, it is the only way human beings can be perfectly happy.

Happiness is largely based on expectations, and part of having an ordered desire and an ordered spiritual life is having proper expectations. Accepting one’s place in the grand scheme of salvation, history, and making peace with the kind of creature one actually is, is essential to happiness. It is sin that makes us unhappy, either because we have sinned within ourselves and due to our own faults, or because we have succumbed to temptation from outside of ourselves. In either case the sin is voluntary, especially seeing that willingly committed evil is the very definition of sin. Evil acts are never not evil, but they are sinful inasmuch as we consent to them by our own free will. When we sin, we corrupt ourselves since we were created to be good, and our nature is objectively good and ordered to the good. Sin wounds our nature and causes us to tend towards sinfulness and non-being, but it does not destroy our nature and cause us to be different kinds of beings.

Condemnation is justly meted out to us when we choose to direct our minds away from God and towards the lesser goods of this world in his place. This is the meaning of idolatry, setting up a creature in the place of the creator. When Augustine says that we owe it to God as creator to use our wills in the manner in which they were designed, this is the meaning of true worship: rational thinking is an act of worship, and sin and forgetfulness is an act of idolatry, allowing the goodness of the creator to drift out of our consciousness. In the end, Augustine concludes, humans can only strive to reverse the curse of Adam and Eve by clinging to Christ and by refusing to use their wills in a manner unworthy of God.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text